Introduction

Justice has been central to political philosophy for over two thousand years. Political thinkers have portrayed a “just good society” as a “just” society. However, there has been far less agreement about what justice stands for. 

In everyday language, justice is used so imprecisely that it is taken to mean ‘fairness’, ‘rightness’, or that which is morally correct. Without a doubt, justice is a moral or normative concept; that which is “just” is certainly morally “good,” and to call something “unjust” is to condemn it as morally “bad.”

However, justice does not simply mean ‘moral.’ Instead, it indicates a particular kind of moral judgment, in particular one about the distribution of rewards and punishments.

Justice, in short, is about giving each person what he or she is “due.” However, it is much more challenging to define what that “due” might be. Justice is perhaps the archetypal example of an ‘essentially contested concept’. No settled or objective concept of justice exists, only a set of competing concepts.

Moreover, although justice is a distributive concept, it is less clear what it is trying to distribute.

What rewards and penalties does the concept of justice address? 

Justice could concern itself with the distribution of almost anything: wealth, income, leisure, liberty, friendship, sexual love, etc.

The concept of justice could be applied to the distribution of any “goods,” but there is no reason why the same principle of distribution should be considered “just” in each case.

For example, those who advocate an equal distribution of material wealth may nevertheless regard the idea of an equal distribution of sexual love as quite bizarre, if not as frankly unjust. In that sense, it is pretty impossible to construct an overriding principle of justice applicable to all areas of life.

As Walzer argued, different principles of justice may, therefore, be appropriate in different spheres of life. During the twentieth century, for instance, justice was usually discussed concerning social life in general and the distribution of material rewards in particular. This thing is what we know as “social justice.”

However, justice is discussed primarily in relation to the law and, therefore, through the concept of “legal justice.” Legal justice concerns how the law distributes penalties for wrong-doing or allocates compensation for injury or damage. Justice in this sense involves creating and enforcing a public set of rules, but to be “just”, these rules must themselves have a moral underpinning.

Forms of Justice in the Legal Process

Two forms of justice can be identified at work in the legal process. 

  • Procedural Justice relates to how the rules are made and applied.
  • Substantive Justice is concerned with the rules themselves and whether they are ‘just’ or ‘unjust’.

Questions about justice in either of these senses are crucial because they bear on the issue of legitimacy. People recognise the law as binding, and so acknowledge an obligation to obey it precisely because they believe it to be just.

If, however, the law is not administered in accordance with justice, or the law itself is seen as unjust, citizens may possess a moral justification for breaking it.

Procedural Justice

Procedural or “formal” justice refers to the manner in which decisions or outcomes are achieved, as opposed to the content of the decisions themselves. Some argue that legal justice is less concerned with the outcomes of law – judgments, verdicts, sentences, and so on – and more concerned with how these outcomes are reached.

There is no doubt that, on certain occasions, justice is entirely a procedural matter. A just and acceptable outcome is guaranteed by the application of particular procedural rules. This clearly applies, for example, in the case of sporting competition. The object of a running race is to establish, quite simply, who is the fastest runner. In this respect, justice is achieved if procedural rules are applied which ensure that all factors other than running talent are irrelevant to the outcome of the race.

Thus, justice demands that every competitor run the same distance, that they start at the same time, that none enjoy an unfair advantage gained through performance-enhancing drugs, that officials adjudicating the race are impartial, and so on.

Legal systems can claim to be just if they operate according to an established set of rules designed to ensure a just outcome. In short, justice is “seen to be done.” These procedural rules can, however, take one of two forms. In the case of what John Rawls called “pure procedural justice,” the question of justice is solely determined by the application of just procedures, as with the example of a running race or a lottery.

In a court of law, there is prior knowledge of what would constitute a just outcome, in which case the justice of the procedures consists of their tendency to produce that outcome. For example, in a criminal trial, the procedural rules are designed to ensure that the guilty are punished, that punishment fits the crime, and so forth.

Many of these procedural rules are, however, not exclusive to the legal system but also apply to other areas of life, ranging from the formal debate in legislative chambers or committees to informal discussions among friends or family. Indeed, it is often suggested that these rules reflect a widely held and perhaps innate sense of what is fair or reasonable, what is usually called “natural” justice. This can be seen, for instance, in the widespread belief that it is fair in argument and debate for all parties to have the opportunity to express their views, or when decisions are taken for those affected by them to be consulted beforehand. Because the fairness of such rules is considered by many to be self-evident, there is often considerable agreement about what makes the administration of law procedurally just.

At the heart of procedural justice stands the principle of formal equality. The law should be applied in a manner that does not discriminate against individuals on grounds like gender, race, religion, or social background. This, in turn, requires that the law be impartially applied, which can only be achieved if judges are strictly independent and unbiased. Where the judiciary has clear political sympathies, as in the case of the US Supreme Court, or when judges are thought to be biassed because they are predominantly male, white, and wealthy, this may be seen as a cause of injustice.

The widespread use of the jury system, at least in criminal cases, may also be justified in terms of procedural justice. The virtue of trial by jury is that juries are randomly selected and so are likely to be impartial and to be capable of applying a standard of justice commonly held in society. The defendant is judged by his or her ‘peers’.

Moreover, the legal system must acknowledge the possibility that mistakes can be made and provide some mechanism through which these can be rectified. This is achieved in practice through a hierarchy of courts, higher courts being able to consider appeals from lower courts.

However, miscarriages of justice may be more difficult to rectify when the process of appeal is placed entirely in the hands of the judges, who may fear bringing the court system, and the judiciary itself, into disrepute. This was highlighted in the UK by the cases of the Guildford Four and the Birmingham Six, whose convictions for terrorism were overturned in 1989 and 1991, but only after they had served 14 and 16 years in jail, respectively.

Procedural justice is also said to require the presumption that the accused is “innocent until proved guilty.” This has been described as the “golden thread” running through the English legal system and those derived from it.

The presumption of innocence ensures that the mere fact of an accusation does not in itself constitute proof; the onus is on the prosecution to offer evidence which can prove guilt beyond “reasonable doubt.” This is also why certain evidence, for instance about the accused’s previous criminal record, may be inadmissible in court since it could taint the jury’s views and prevent a verdict being reached on the ‘facts of the case’.

In the same way, an accused person has traditionally been accorded a right to silence, on the grounds that it is the prosecution’s job to establish guilt. In the USA, for example, this is enshrined in the Fifth Amendment of the Constitution, which guarantees the right to avoid self-incrimination.

The principle of equal treatment has applications at every point in the legal process. For example, it suggests that ordinary citizens should not be disadvantaged by their ignorance when dealing with the police, the prosecution, or the judiciary. It is normally accepted, therefore, that an accused person should be clearly informed about the charges made against him or her, and that he or she should be informed at the outset about their rights, notably their right to legal advice. Such rules of procedural justice have been most clearly defined in the USA.

For example, in Miranda v. Arizona (1966), the Supreme Court laid down very strict procedures which the police have to follow when questioning suspects; and in Gideon v. Wainwright (1963), it guaranteed defendants the right to a lawyer, regardless of their financial circumstances. In other cases, however, governments have ignored such principles in the belief that they unnecessarily hamper the pursuit of criminals or others who threaten public order.

In the UK, the Terrorism Act 2001, passed in the aftermath of the terrorist attacks on New York and Washington, included the power to hold terrorist suspects without trial, infringing on the right to liberty as set out in the Human Rights Act 1998.

Substantive Justice

As pointed out earlier, the requirements of legal justice cannot be entirely met by the application of procedural rules, however fair these rules may be and however scrupulously they may be applied. This is the sense in which the law is different from competitive sport; its outcomes, and not merely its procedures, are claimed to be just.

The legal process may thus generate injustice not because the law is unfairly applied but because the law itself is unjust.

For instance, laws that prohibit women from voting or that ban ethnic minorities from owning property are not made “just” by the fact that they are applied by courts whose procedures are fair and impartial. The content of the law must, therefore, be judged in the light of a principle of substantive or “concrete” justice.

Whereas there is considerable agreement about the rules of procedural justice, the same cannot be said of substantive justice. Legal justice has traditionally been linked to the idea that law aims to treat people according to their “just deserts”, or, in the words of the Roman Emperor Justinian, justice means “giving each man his due”. The difficulty of doing this was illustrated by the earlier discussion of competing theories of punishment.

Supporters of retribution may argue that, in principle, justice demands that the murderer’s life be forfeited in punishment for his crime; those who advocate deterrence may accept capital punishment but only when empirical evidence indicates that it will reduce the number of murders; rehabilitation theorists reject capital punishment in all circumstances, regarding it as little more than a form of legalised murder. No amount of debate and analysis is likely to shift any of these positions because they are based on fundamentally different moral principles.

The same applies to the attempt to distribute material rewards justly. While some argue that social justice requires a high level of material equality on the grounds that wealth should be distributed according to individual needs, others are happy to accept a high level of material inequality so long as it is based upon the unequal talents of the people involved.

Like all normative principles, the idea of substantive justice is subjective; at heart, it is a matter of opinion. Notions of justice, therefore, vary from individual to individual, from group to group, from society to society, and from period to period. Indeed, the decline of religion and traditional values, and the growth of both social and geographical mobility, has encouraged the development of moral pluralism. Ethical and cultural diversity make it impossible to make any firm or authoritative judgements about the moral content of the law or to establish reliable criteria for distinguishing just laws from unjust ones. Justice is, in this sense, a relative concept. It perhaps has meaning only for particular individuals or groups, and cannot be applied to society at large.

One way around this problem is to try to relate justice to a set of dominant or commonly held values in society. This is precisely what Patrick Devlin (1968) meant when he proposed that the law should “enforce morality.”

In Devlin’s view, the law is based upon the moral values of the average citizen, or, in his words, “the man on the Clapham omnibus.” Thus, he proposed a distinction between what he called “consensus laws” and “non-consensus laws.” Consensus laws are ones that conform to commonly held standards of fairness or justice; they are laws that, in Devlin’s view, people are “prepared to put up with.”

On the other hand, non-consensus laws are widely regarded as unacceptable or unjust, which is normally reflected by the fact of widespread disobedience. Devlin did not go as far as to suggest that breaking non-consensus laws was justified, but he nevertheless warned that their enforcement would only bring the judiciary and the legal process into disrepute.

An example of non-consensus law might be the ‘poll tax’ in the UK, which, when introduced in England and Wales in 1990, gave rise to a widespread campaign of protest and non-payment, based upon the belief that the tax violated generally held views of social justice.

Devlin believed that judges, who are strictly impartial and stand apart from the political process, are in the best position to apply the distinction between consensus and non-consensus law. After all, judges have had years of experience adjudicating disputes and arbitrating between conflicting interpretations of the law.

However, this form of judicial activism has proved to be highly controversial, as it allows non-elected judges to make decisions that have a clear moral and political content. The issue has been particularly relevant in the United States in view of the widely acknowledged role of the Supreme Court in making public policy.

During the New Deal period of the 1930s, for instance, the Court struck down important social welfare programs. In the 1950s and 1960s, however, the Warren Court was responsible for advancing civil rights on a number of fronts. The danger of such “activism”, however, is that there is no way of knowing whether judges’ interpretations of the law reflect widely held views about what is right or acceptable or simply their own personal beliefs. It is clear that, since they are not elected, their definition of consensus morality enjoys no electoral mandate. Moreover, in the light of the socially unrepresentative nature of the judiciary, it is questionable that the judges know much about what Devlin called “the man on the Clapham omnibus.”

Regardless of who is empowered to define consensus morality, there are reasons to believe that the idea itself may not stand up to serious scrutiny. In the first place, it implies that a reliable distinction can be made between consensus and non-consensus laws. In practice, few, if any, issues provoke widespread agreement, much less unanimity.

All governments pass legislation that is politically controversial in that it provokes protests or at least a significant measure of criticism. This could be applied to almost every area of government policy: economic management, taxation, industrial relations, education, health, housing, law and order, race relations, and so on.

The danger of Devlin’s argument is that it threatens to classify most laws as non-consensus on the grounds that somebody or other is not “prepared to put up with” them. This leads to difficult questions about how many people need to object, and what form their objections need to take, before a law can be regarded as non-consensual. Such difficulties, however, merely reflect a deeper problem. In many respects, the idea of a consensus morality is simply a hangover from the days of traditional and homogeneous communities.

In modern societies, characterised by ethnic, religious, racial, cultural, and moral pluralism, any attempt to identify consensus beliefs is doomed to failure.

Justifying law-breaking?

The question ‘Why should I obey the law?’ It elicits from many people the simple response: ‘Because it is the law.’ The law, in other words, is usually acknowledged to be legitimate, in the sense that most citizens accept an obligation to obey it. The law is therefore recognised as binding upon those to whom it applies.

In a formal sense, the law is the law only because it is obeyed – at least by the vast majority of the population. There is thus a sense in which laws remaining on the statute book but which are no longer obeyed or enforced cease to be law. This applies, perhaps, in the case of copyright laws that prohibit the taping of audio or video cassettes and, in some countries, laws which ban the use of so-called “soft” drugs like cannabis. Indeed, in countries such as the Netherlands, an attempt has been made to formalise this anomaly by “decriminalizing” the use of “soft” drugs.

Nevertheless, despite the general acknowledgment that the law is legitimate, it is clear that all laws are broken to some degree—otherwise, the machinery of law enforcement would simply be redundant. It is important to acknowledge, however, that incidents of law-breaking fall into two separate categories.

In most cases, laws are broken by people described, rather quaintly, as’ common criminals’. Common criminals seldom put forward a moral justification for their actions and rarely portray their behaviour as anything other than naked self-seeking. Criminal behaviour of this kind undoubtedly raises some interesting questions, for example, about the psychological or social factors which help to explain law-breaking and the possible means through which others can be deterred from pursuing the same course.

However, these are descriptive questions about why the law is obeyed or why it is not obeyed. However reluctant they may be to be caught or prosecuted, so-called common criminals usually acknowledge that they should have obeyed the law and so recognise the law as binding.

On the other hand, there are incidents of law-breaking that are principled and, maybe, justifiable in moral or political terms. Some legal systems, indeed, acknowledge this fact by categorising certain law-breakers as “political prisoners” and treating them differently from everyday criminals.

The distinction between the two may, however, be both unclear and politically controversial. This has been evident in the case of terrorist groups, such as the IRA in the UK and ETA, the Basque separatist movement in Spain, which have at different times aspired to be granted ‘political status’ on the grounds that they are not criminals but ‘freedom fighters’.

Some go further and extend the notion of “political” crimes to include criminal acts that result from social circumstances like deprivation, poverty, or inequality, even though their perpetrators may not claim any conscious political motivation.

Anarchists, in fact, are not prepared to recognise any distinction between criminal and political offenses, in that they regard all laws as immoral and therefore tend to see the moral justification in every case of law-breaking.

The moral justification for law-breaking can be examined in two ways.

One is to ask the question: “Why should I obey the law?” The alternative is to turn the question on its head and ask: “What justification is there for breaking the law?”

This raises the issue of “civil disobedience,” which is defined as law-breaking justified by religious, moral, or political principles. Civil disobedience has a long and respectable heritage, drawing as it does upon the ideas of writers such as Henry David Thoreau (1817–62) and the examples of political leaders such as Mahatma Gandhi and Martin Luther King (1929–68).

Under Gandhi’s influence, non-violent civil disobedience became a powerful weapon in the campaign for Indian independence, finally granted in 1947. In the early 1960s, Martin Luther King adopted similar political tactics in the struggle for black civil rights in the American South.

Civil disobedience is an overt and public act: it aims to break a law in order to ‘make a point’ rather than in an attempt to get away with it. Civil disobedience is thus distinguished from other criminal acts by its motives, which are conscientious or principled in the sense that they aim to bring about some kind of legal or political change; it does not merely serve the interests of the law-breaker himself or herself. Indeed, in many cases, it is precisely the willing acceptance of the penalties that law-breaking involves that gives civil disobedience its moral authority and emotional power.

Finally, at least in the tradition of Thoreau, Gandhi, and King, civil disobedience is non-violent, a fact which helps to underline the moral character of the act itself. Gandhi was particularly insistent upon this, calling his form of non-violent, non-cooperation, satyagraha, literally meaning defence of, and by, the truth. Civil disobedience thus stands apart from a very different tradition of political law-breaking, which takes the form of popular revolt, terrorism, and revolution.

In some cases, civil disobedience may involve the breaking of laws which are themselves considered to be wicked or unjust, its aim being to protest against the law in question and achieve its removal. In other cases, however, it involves breaking the law in order to protest against a wider injustice, even though the law being broken may not itself be objectionable. An example of the former would be the burning of draught cards or the refusal to pay that proportion of taxation which is devoted to military purposes, forms of protest adopted by opponents of the Vietnam War in the USA.

Similarly, Sikhs in the UK openly flouted the law compelling motorcyclists to wear crash-helmets because it threatened their religious duty to wear turbans. On the other hand, Thoreau, who refused all payment of taxes in an act of protest against the Mexican–American War of the 1840s and the continuation of slavery in the South, is an example of the latter.

On some occasions, Gandhi combined the two goals. In his famous movement, “march to the sea” or “Dandi March”, in 1930, for instance, he sought to protest against the law banning Indians from making salt by making a symbolic amount of salt from seawater and thus courting arrest, but only as part of a larger campaign for national independence.

Whether it is designed to attack a particular law or advance a wider cause, all acts of civil disobedience are justified by asserting a distinction between law and justice. The belief that the individual, rather than the government, is the ultimate moral authority is at the heart of civil disobedience; to believe otherwise would imply that all laws are just and reduce justice to mere legality.

The distinction between law and justice has usually, in the modern period, been based upon the doctrine of human rights, asserting as it does that there is a set of higher moral principles against which human law can be judged and to which it should conform.

Individuals are therefore justified in breaking the law to highlight violations of human rights or to challenge laws that themselves threaten human rights.

Other justifications for civil disobedience focus on the nature of the political process and the lack of alternative (legal) opportunities for expressing views and exerting pressure. For example, few would fail to sympathise with the actions of those who in Nazi Germany broke the law by sheltering Jews or assisting their passage out of the country. This applies not only because of the morally repulsive nature of the laws concerned but also because, in a fascist dictatorship, no form of legal or constitutional protest was possible.

Similarly, the use of civil disobedience to gain votes for women in the 19th and early 20th centuries can be justified by the simple fact that, deprived of the right to vote, women had no other way of making their voices heard. Civil disobedience campaigns were also used to achieve black suffrage in the American South and South Africa. Even when universal suffrage exists, it can perhaps be argued that the ballot box alone does not ensure that individual and minority rights are respected.

Even if they have formal political rights, a permanent minority, such as the Catholic community in Northern Ireland, may resort to civil disobedience and, at times, support political violence. Finally, it is sometimes argued that democratic and electoral politics may simply be too slow or time-consuming to provide an adequate means of exerting political pressure when human life itself is under imminent threat. This is, for example, the case made out by anti-nuclear campaigners and environmental activists, both of whom believe that the urgency of their cause overrides what by comparison appears to be the almost trivial obligation to obey the law.

Since the 1960s, civil disobedience has become more widespread and politically acceptable. In some respects, it is now regarded as a constitutional act that aims to correct a specific wrong and is prepared to conform to a set of established rules, notably about peaceful non-violence.

For example, civil disobedience is now accepted by many as a legitimate weapon available to pressure groups. Sit-ins or sit-down protests help to attract publicity and demonstrate the strength of protesters’ convictions, and may, in turn, help to promote public sympathy. Of course, such acts may also be counter-productive, making the individuals or groups concerned appear irresponsible or extremist. In these cases, the question of civil disobedience becomes a tactical matter rather than a moral one.

Critics of the principle nevertheless argue that it brings with it a number of insidious dangers. The first of these is that, as civil disobedience becomes fashionable, it threatens to undermine respect for an alternative, legal and democratic means of exerting influence. At a deeper level, however, the spread of civil disobedience may ultimately threaten both social order and political stability by eroding the fear of illegality. When people cease obeying the law automatically and only do so out of personal choice, the authority of the law itself is brought into question. As a result, acts of civil disobedience may gradually weaken the principles upon which a regime is based and so be linked to rebellion and even revolution. This was evident in 1989, when a mounting wave of illegal but usually peaceful demonstrations in countries such as East Germany and what was then Czechoslovakia led eventually to the collapse of their political regimes.

Categorized in: